« Approfondissements de lycée/Infini et processus infinis » : différence entre les versions

Contenu supprimé Contenu ajouté
Début de traduction de l'article anglais
 
Aucun résumé des modifications
Ligne 31 :
 
====Exemple====
Soit <math>\mathbb{N}\,</math> l'ensemble des nombres courants. <math>\mathbb{N}\,</math> est appelé l'ensemble des nombres naturels. 1,2,3,4,5,6, ... "jusqu'à" l'infini.
Let Set N be all counting numbers. N is called the set of natural numbers. 1,2,3,4,5,6, ... and so to infinity.
Let SetSoit B, bel'ensemble thedes negativenombres numbersnégatifs -1,-2,-3, ... andainsi sode onsuite to"jusqu'à" -infinity l'infini.
Les éléments de <math>\mathbb{N}\,</math> et B peuvent-ils être appariés ? La manières formelle de dire cela est "Peut-on mettre A et B en bijection ?"
Can the members of N and B be paired up? The formal way of saying this is "Can A and B be put into a one to one correspondance"?
 
Evidemment, la réponse est oui. 1 de l'ensemble <math>\mathbb{N}\,</math> correspond à -1 de B. Comme suit :
Obviously the answer is yes. 1 in set N corresponds with -1 in B. Likewise:
:'''N''' &nbsp; '''B'''
:1 &nbsp; -1
Ligne 42 :
and so on.
 
L'ensemble des nombres naturels est si utile que tout ensemble qui peut être mis en bijection avec lui est dit ''infini dénombrable''.
So useful is the set of counting numbers that any set that can be put into a one to one correspondence with it is said to be ''countably infinite''.
 
Regardons quelques exemples supplémentaires. L'ensemble des entiers est-il infini dénombrable ?
Let's look at some more examples. Is the set of integers countably infinite?
IntegersLes areentiers setsont l'ensemble N, setl'ensemble B andet 0.
 
... -3,-2,-1, 0, 1, 2, 3, ...
 
Historiquement, cet ensemble est généralement appelé <math>\mathbb{Z}\,</math>. Noter que <math>\mathbb{N}\,</math>, l'ensemble des nombres naturels est un sous-ensemble de <math>\mathbb{Z}\,</math>. Tous les éléments de <math>\mathbb{N}\,</math> sont dans <math>\mathbb{Z}\,</math>, mais tous les éléments de <math>\mathbb{Z}\,</math> ne sont pas dans <math>\mathbb{N}\,</math>.
Historically this set is usually called Z. Note that N the set of natural numbers is a subset of Z. All members of N are in Z, but not all members of Z are in N.
 
Ce que nous avons besoin de savoir est si <math>\mathbb{Z}\,</math> peut être mis en bijection avec <math>\mathbb{N}\,</math>. Notre première réponse, donnée par le fait que <math>\mathbb{N}\,</math> est un sous-ensemble de <math>\mathbb{Z}\,</math>, serait non mais elle serait fausse ! En théorie des ensembles, l' ''ordre'' des éléments n'est pas important. Il n'y a pas de raisons pourquoi nous ne pourrions pas réarranger les éléments dans n'importe quel ordre tant que nous n'en omettons pas. <math>\mathbb{Z}\,</math> présenté comme ci-dessus n'est pas très dénombrable, mais si nous le réécrivons comme 0, -1, 1, -2, 2, -3, 4 ..... et ainsi de suite, nous pouvons voir qu'il est dénombrable.
What we need to find out is if Z can be put into a one to one correspondence with N. Your first answer, given that N is a subset of Z, may be no but you would be wrong! In set theory, the ''order'' of the elements is unimportant. There is no reason why we can't rearrange the elements into any order we please as long as we don't miss any out. Z as presented above doesn't look countable, but if we rewrite it as 0, -1, 1, -2, 2, -3, 4 ..... and so on we can see that it is countable.
 
:'''Z''' &nbsp; '''N'''
Ligne 58 :
: &nbsp;1 &nbsp; 3
: -2 &nbsp; 4
et ainsi de suite. Vraiment étrange ! Un sous-ensemble de <math>\mathbb{Z}\,</math> (nommément les nombres naturels) possède le même nombre d'éléments que <math>\mathbb{Z}\,</math> lui-même ? Les ensembles infinis ne sont pas comme les ensembles ordinaires. En fait, ceci est quelquefois utilisé comme une définition d'un ensemble infini. '''Un ensemble infini est tout ensemble qui peut être mis en bijection avec au moins un de ses sous-ensembles'''. Plutôt que de dire "Le nombre d'éléments" d'un ensemble, on emploie quelquefois le mot '''cardinal''' ou '''valeur cardinale'''. <math>\mathbb{Z}\,</math> et <math>\mathbb{N}\,</math> sont dits avoir le même cardinal.
and so on. Strange indeed! A subset of Z (namely the natural numbers) has the same number of members as Z itself? Infinite sets are not like ordinary finite sets. In fact this is sometimes used as a definition of an infinite set. '''An infinite set is any set which can be put into a one to one correspondence with at least one of its subsets'''. Rather than saying "The number of members" of a set, people sometimes use the word '''cardinality''' or '''cardinal value'''. Z and N are said to have the same cardinality.
 
====ExercisesExercices====
#Is the number of even numbers the same as the natural numbers?
#What about the number of square numbers?
Ligne 66 :
#Using the idea of one to one correspondance prove that infinity + 1 = infinity, what about infinity + A where A is a ''finite'' set? What about infinity plus C where C is a countably infinite set?
 
===IsL'ensemble thedes setnombres ofrationnels rationalest numbersplus biggergrand thanque N ?===
In this section we will look to see if we can find a set that is '''bigger''' than the countable infinity we have looked at so far. To illustrate the idea we can imagine a story.
 
Ligne 89 :
So how do we go about counting Q'? If we try counting the first row then the second and so on we will fail because the rows are infinite in length. Likewise if we try to count columns. But look at the diagonals. In one direction they are infinite ( e.g. 1/1, 2/2, 3/3, ...) but in the other direction they are finite. So this set is countable. We count them along the finite diagonals, 1/1, 1/2, 2/1, 1/3, 2/2, 3/1....
 
====ExercisesExercices====
# Adapt the method of counting the set Q' to show that thet Q is also countable. How will you include 0 and the negative rationals? How will you solve the problem of multiple entries representing the same number ?
# Show that <math> \infty \times \infty = \infty </math> (provided that the infinites are both countable)
 
===CanPouvons-nous wetrouver finddes anyensembles setsplus thatgrands areque biggerN than N?===
 
So far we have looked at N, Z, and Q and found them all to be the same size, even tough N is a subset of Z which is a subset of Q. You might be beginning to think "Is that it? Are all infinities the same size?" In this section we will look at an set that is ''bigger'' than N. A set that ''cannot'' be put into a one to one correspondence with N no matter how it is arranged.
Ligne 109 :
Now imagine you measure a book and found it to be 10.101010101010cm. You'd be pretty surprised wouldn't you? But this is exactly the sort of result you would need to get if the book's length were rational. Rational numbers are dense (you find them all over the number line), infinite, yet much much rarer than real numbers.
 
===HowComment wepouvons-nous candémontrer prove thatque R isest plus biggergrand thanque Q===
It's good to get a feel for the size of infinities as in the previous section. But to be really sure we have to come up with some form of proof. In order to prove that R is bigger than Q we use a classic method. We assume that R is the same size as Q and come up with a contradiction. For the sake of clarity we will restrict our proof to the real numbers between 0 and 1.We will call this set R' Clearly if we can prove that R' is bigger than Q then R must be bigger than Q also.
 
Ligne 147 :
We have done what we set out to do. We have constructed a number that is in R but is not on the "list of all members of R". This means that R is bigger than any list. It is not listable. It is not countable. It is a bigger infinity than Q.
 
===Existe-t'il même des infinis plus grands ?===
===Are there even bigger infinities?===
 
There are but they are difficult to describe. The set of all the possible combinations of any number of real numbers is a bigger infinity than R. However trying to imagine such a set is mind boggling. Let's look instead at a set that looks like it should be bigger than R but turns out not to be.
Ligne 168 :
This defines a one to one correspondence between the points in the plane and the points in the line. (Actually, for the sharp amongst you, not quite one to one. Can you spot the problem and how to cure it?)
 
====ExercisesExercices====
#Prove the the number of points in a cube is the same as the number of points on one of its sides.
 
===ContinuumL'hypothèse hypothesisdu continu===
 
We shall end the section on infinite sets by looking at the Continuum hypothesis. This hypothesis states that there are no infinities between the natural numbers and the real numbers. Cantor came up with a number system for transfinite numbers. He called the smallest infinity <math>\aleph_0</math> with the next biggest one <math>\aleph_1</math> and so on. It is easy to prove that the cardinality of N is <math>\aleph_0</math> (Write any smaller infinity out as a list. Either the list terminates, in which case it's finite, or it goes on forever, in which case it's the same size as N) but is the cardinality of the reals = <math>\aleph_1</math>?
Ligne 180 :
The hypothesis is interesting because it has been proved that "It is not possible to prove the hypothesis true or false, using the normal axioms of set theory"
 
===FurtherLectures readingplus poussées===
If you want to learn more about set theory or infinite sets try one of the many interesting pages on our sister project [[en:wikipedia]].
*[http://en2.wikipedia.org/wiki/Ordinal_number ordinal numbers]
Ligne 187 :
*[http://en2.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hilbert%27s_paradox_of_the_Grand_Hotel Hilbert's Hotel]
 
==LimitsLimites : ''Infinitycomment gotéviter rid ofl'infini''==
The theory of infinite sets seems weird to us in the 21st century, but in Cantor's day it was downright unpalatable for most mathematicians. In those days the idea of infinity was too troublesome, they tried to avoid it wherever possible.
 
Ligne 208 :
Note that we are not dividing 1 by infinity and getting the answer 0. We are letting the number ''n'' get bigger and bigger and so the reciprocal gets closer and closer to zero. Those 18th Century mathematicians loved this idea because it got rid of the pesky idea of ''dividing by infinity''. At all times ''n'' remains finite. Of course, no matter how huge ''n'' is, 1/''n'' will not be ''exactly'' equal to zero, there is always a small difference. This difference (or error) is usually denoted by &epsilon; (epsilon).
 
===info -- infinitelyinfiniment smallpetit===
<blockquote style="padding: 1em; border: 2px dotted purple;">
When we talk about infinity, we think of it as something big. But there is also the infinitely small, denoted by &epsilon; (epsilon). This animal is closer to zero than any other number. Mathematicians also use the character &epsilon; to represent anything small. For example, the famous Hungarian mathematician Paul Erdos used to refer to small children as epsilons.
</blockquote>
 
===ExamplesExemples===
Lets look at the function
:<math> \frac{x^2 + x}{x^2} </math>
Ligne 245 :
:<math>\lim_{x \to \infty}\frac{1}{x}(\sin x) = 0 </math>
 
===ExercisesExercices===
 
 
Ligne 255 :
#<math>\lim_{x \to \infty}(2x^2 -x^4) </math>
 
==InfiniteSéries seriesinfinies==
Consider the infinite sum 1/1 + 1/2 + 1/4 + 1/8 + 1/16 + ....
Do you think that this sum will equal infinity once all the terms have been added ? Let's sum the first few terms.
Ligne 273 :
Here is another way of looking at it. Imagine a point on a number line moving along as the sum progresses. In the first term the point jumps to the position 1. This is half way from 0 to 2. In the second stage the point jumps to position 1.5 - half way from 1 to 2. At each stage in the process (shown in a different colour on the diagram) the distance to 2 is halved. The point can get as close to the point 2 as you like. You just need to do the appropriate number of jumps, but the point will never actually reach 2 in a finite number of steps. We say than in the limit as n approaches infinity, S<sub>n</sub> approaches 2.
 
===Zeno'sParadoxe Paradoxde Zenon===
The ancient Greeks had a big problem with summing infinite series. A famous paradox from the philosopher Zeno is as follows: